Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011, pp. 176–185
Relative thinking in consumer choice between differentiated goods
and services and its implications for business strategy
The article shows that when people consider differentiated goods or services that differ in price and quality, they
exhibit a decision-making bias of “relative thinking”: relative price differences affect them even when economic theorysuggests that only absolute price differences matter. This result is obtained in four different consumption categories. Sometimes subjects are affected only by relative price differences (“full relative thinking”) and sometimes also byabsolute price differences (“partial relative thinking”). This behavior has implications for various disciplines, and it isparticularly relevant in models dealing with horizontal or vertical differentiation, optimal pricing, competitive strategy,or advertising. Keywords: relative thinking; consumer behavior; product differentiation; judgment and decision making.
tion. The reduction in wealth following the purchase ofthe high-quality good is related to the absolute price dif-
One of the most common decision problems that con-
ference between the goods, and not to the relative price
sumers face is choosing between differentiated goods or
services that differ in their quality and price. Such situ-
The result of this idea is that, absent wealth effects, the
ations exist in almost any category of goods or services,
good’s price should not affect the willingness to pay for
ranging from the choice of cheese or a hotel room to the
a given quality improvement. The principle that only ab-
choice of a car or a house. For almost any purchase de-
solute price differences should matter in such consumer
cision we make, we have several alternatives, and usu-
decisions follows from rational utility maximization and
ally these alternatives differ in their quality and price.
is an unchallenged assumption in the theoretical literature
This implies that understanding how consumers choose
in economics on product differentiation (both vertical and
between differentiated goods is of great importance.
horizontal). Tirole (1988, p. 96), for example, models
When a consumer wants to buy one unit of a good and
vertical product differentiation (differentiation where one
he has to choose between two differentiated goods, eco-
good is clearly better than the other—but is also more
nomic theory suggests that the absolute price difference
expensive) using a framework in which the consumer’s
matters while the relative price difference does not. This
surplus when buying a good with quality s at price p is
is because the opportunity cost of obtaining the higher
θs−p. It follows that when the consumer faces two differ-
quality (by purchasing the more expensive good) comes
entiated goods, he prefers good 1 if θs1 − p1 > θs2 − p2,
from the reduced wealth that is left for other consump-
or equivalently, if θ(s1 − s2) > p1 − p2. It is easy tosee that this expression involves the absolute price differ-
I thank the Editor Jon Baron and two anonymous referees for their
helpful comments. I am also grateful to David Balan, seminar par-
ence (p1 − p2) but not the relative price difference (e.g.,
ticipants at the University of Copenhagen, the Interdisciplinary Cen-
(p1 − p2)/p1 or (p1 − p2)/p2). Additional examples that
ter Herzliya and the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, and conference
illustrate that economics models assume that only abso-
participants in the 22nd Israel Economic Association Annual Confer-
lute price differences matter are models of horizontal dif-
ence, the 33rd EARIE Annual Conference, the 2006 ESA EuropeanRegional Meeting, the Affect, Motivation and Decision Making Interna-
ferentiation (horizontal differentiation exists when there
tional Conference in the Dead Sea, the 2007 ESA Asia-Pacific Regional
is no clear advantage of one good over the other in terms
Meeting and the 2009 ESA European Regional Meeting for helpful
of quality, and different customers have different prefer-
comments. Financial support from the Russell Sage Foundation and the
ences between them), such as the linear city (Hotelling,
Phillipe Monaster Center for Economic Research at Ben-Gurion Uni-versity of the Negev is gratefully acknowledged. I thank Michal Barry,
1929) or the circular city (Salop, 1979). In these two sem-
Michal Baruch, Galit Dori, Tom Harel, and Tamar Kugler for valuable
inal articles, and others that followed them, the absolute
price difference between the differentiated goods is again
∗Department of Business Administration, Guilford Glazer Faculty
of Business and Management, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev,
crucial, but the relative price difference plays no role in
P.O.B. 653, Beer-Sheva 84105, Israel. Email: [email protected].
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
Despite the widespread use of the assumption that only
ity theory, was supported. Grewal and Marmorstein sug-
absolute price differences matter when choosing between
gest that the psychological utility that consumers derive
differentiated goods, however, it is not clear whether peo-
from saving a certain amount is inversely related to the
ple indeed behave according to this principle. A related
good’s price. Darke et al. (1995) examine consumer price
issue is discussed in the literature that deals with how
search and find that consumers used the percentage dis-
the trade-off between time and money changes as prices
count as a heuristic cue to help decide whether a better
change. Thaler (1980), for example, conjectures that peo-
price was likely to be available elsewhere when the ini-
ple exert more effort to save $5 on a $25 radio than to save
tial base price of the item was low, but not when it was
$5 on a $500 TV.1 Later, in line with Thaler’s conjec-
high. Heath et al. (1995) are interested in how consumers
ture, several experimental studies found that people are
perceive changes in a good’s price. They examine the ef-
more willing to invest a certain time in order to save a
fects of percentage-based frames on price perceptions and
constant dollar amount when the good’s price is lower.
preferences for multiple price changes (price increases
Tversky and Kahneman (1981), for example, asked sub-
on one good together with price reductions on a sec-
jects whether they would be willing to drive 20 minutes to
ond good). They report that mental accounting principles
save $5 on a calculator in a hypothetical scenario where
generally prevailed in the absence of percentage-based
they were told that they wanted to purchase a calculator
frames, and that mental accounting principles, price per-
and a jacket. 68% of the subjects were willing to drive 20
ception and reference dependence are sensitive to how
minutes to save $5 on a $15 calculator (when they also
deviations from reference states are framed.
were hypothetically buying a $125 jacket), but only 29%
Baron (1997) reports that subjects were less willing to
chose to do so when the $5 saving was on a $125 cal-
pay for government medical insurance for diseases when
culator (and they also were hypothetically buying a $15
the number of people who could not be cured was higher,
holding constant the number who could be cured. In an-
Tversky and Kahneman’s result was later replicated in
other experiment he found that the description of risk
several other studies. Mowen and Mowen (1986) showed
in terms of percentage or the number of lives saved did
that the effect holds similarly for student subjects and for
not affect the willingness to pay for risk reduction, even
business managers subjects. Frisch (1993) demonstrated
though subjects knew that the risks differed in preva-
that the effect holds also when only a calculator is being
lence. Baron suggests that these results can be explained
purchased, and Ranyard and Abdel-Nabi (1993) varied
in terms of a general tendency to confuse proportions and
the price of the jacket and obtained similar results. Darke
differences. Fetherstonhaugh et al. (1997) find that an in-
and Freedman (1993) found in one experiment that per-
tervention saving a fixed number of lives was judged sig-
centage off played no role on effort to save money, but in
nificantly more beneficial when fewer lives were at risk
a second experiment with a greater range of percentages
that could be saved they found that the percentage dis-
DelVecchio (2005) finds that deal-prone consumers are
count had an effect on consumer choice. Azar (in press)
sensitive to the value of a promotion relative to other
used nine different prices and five different goods and
available promotions only in a condition of high abso-
elicited the exact price for which the subject is indiffer-
lute dollar savings. Bartel (2006) presents scenarios that
ent between the two stores (one requiring him to spend
include a tradeoff between absolute and relative savings,
20 more minutes). This allowed him to estimate that the
for example saving more human or animal lives versus
compensation people require for the effort of going to the
saving a larger proportion of a population. Choices were
remote other store is roughly proportional to the square
driven by both the absolute and relative savings. Maxi-
mizing relative savings at the expense of absolute savings
Other studies that address related issues include Gre-
is non-normative, and most subjects agree with this argu-
wal and Marmorstein (1994), who test two possible ex-
ment upon reflection. Svenson (2008) shows that people
planations why consumers’ willingness to engage in price
consider ratios that are irrelevant also in decisions about
search does not increase with the price dispersion. The
which option can save more time (e.g., in saving travel-
first potential explanation was that consumers underes-
ling time in road traffic or saving doctors’ time in reorga-
timate the market price dispersion, and it was not sup-
nizing clinics). Kogut and Beyth-Marom (2008) ask sub-
ported. The second explanation, which is based on We-
jects to rate the importance of two pieces of information,
ber’s law of psychophysics and Thaler’s transaction util-
one stating the number of people that a certain program
1The corresponding principle in psychophysics, known as Weber’s
can save, and the other stating the percentage of people
Law (or Weber-Fechner Law), states that people’s ability to discrim-
that can be saved. They find that when subjects are asked
inate between physical stimuli depends on the relative difference be-
about their own judgment, they give more importance to
tween them and not on the absolute difference. However, this does notnecessarily imply that the same is true when we consider numbers in
the absolute number of people saved, but, when subjects
decision problems, rather than physical stimuli.
are asked to predict how the average student rates the im-
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
portance of each piece of information, they predict that
ing on the proportion saved does not reduce his physical
the proportion of lives saved is more important. Hom-
well-being.2 On the other hand, making biased decisions
burg et al. (2010) study the impact of price increases on
about one’s consumption alternatives does affect the de-
future purchase behavior and find that the framing of a
cision maker’s well-being. This is another reason that we
price increase as a percentage leads to a lower likelihood
may not observe relative thinking in choice between dif-
of a future purchase compared to the framing in absolute
ferentiated goods even if proportions play a role in deci-
sions about saving lives. Consequently, it is important to
The study reported in this article examines whether
examine whether relative thinking exists in the context
consumers consider relative or absolute price differences
of choosing between differentiated goods even though
when choosing between differentiated products. The re-
we already know that proportions matter in choosing be-
sults show that people do not choose between differen-
tiated goods by comparing their valuation of the quality
As the literature review above suggested, much of the
difference to the absolute price difference, as economic
literature discussed the context of saving lives, but an-
theory prescribes. Instead, when people make purchase
other major context that was explored is that of decid-
decisions, the relative price difference (measured here as
ing whether to spend time to find a cheaper price for the
the absolute price difference divided by the price of the
same good (either when it is known that such a cheaper
high-quality good) plays a crucial role. Consequently,
store exists but requires travel, or in the context of price
people are willing to pay more for the same quality dif-
search where other prices are unknown). This context is
ference, when the good’s price is higher. This behavior
significantly different from the context of choosing be-
represents a decision making bias that was recently de-
tween differentiated goods. In the first case, the con-
noted “relative thinking” (Azar, 2004). Because choos-
sumer buys the exact same good, but can buy it in differ-
ing between differentiated goods is so common in real
ent stores. In the differentiated goods context, the goods
life, this is an important finding about consumer behav-
are different (and the store may or may not be the same
ior, with implications for research in marketing, decision
one).3 This difference results in substantially different
science, psychology, economics and other related disci-
decision and considerations. The choice between differ-
plines, as well as for businesses and managers.
entiated goods requires the consumer to consider to what
This study is different from the previous literature de-
extent the higher-quality good yields a higher utility for
scribed above in several ways. The context of choos-
him, and how much money it is worth paying to obtain
ing between differentiated goods is very different from
the better quality. The decision whether to spend time to
the context of choosing between programs to save lives.
find a cheaper price for the same good requires the deci-
Consumption of goods and services is different from sav-
sion maker to evaluate in monetary terms the value of his
ing lives. Comparing number of lives is different from
time and effort. Evaluating the value of increased quality
comparing prices. Deciding which of two differentiated
is very different from estimating the value of one’s time
goods to buy is something that an average adult does on a
and effort, and it is not clear that a behavior of relative
daily basis; almost every time we buy lunch, toothpaste,
thinking in the domain of price search or travelling to a
bread, etc., we choose among several alternatives. On the
cheaper store necessarily implies that it will also exist in
other hand, deciding which program to adopt to save lives
choices between differentiated goods. Moreover, even in
is a decision that most people do not make even once in
the context of spending time to find a lower price some
a lifetime. Therefore the experience one has in making
studies showed that relative thinking is not always present
these decisions is vastly different. It could certainly be
(e.g., Darke & Freedman, 1993; Darke et al., 1995).
the case that in a decision to save lives, which the sub-
This study is also different from the literature discussed
ject encounters for the first time in his life, he is biased
above in additional ways. Instead of making a binary
and is affected by proportions, but in a decision on choos-
choice (e.g., between two life-saving programs or be-
ing between differentiated goods (something that he did
tween driving 20 minutes and spending $5 more), sub-
many times), his experience can help him to do the ratio-
2In addition, in some contexts, the proportion of lives saved is also
nal thing and focus on the absolute price difference, ig-
highly relevant, and this can create a heuristic decision rule that is then
noring the irrelevant relative price difference. Moreover,
applied also when it is irrelevant. For example, most people would
the desire to save lives is motivated by altruism; the lives
agree that it is more important to save ten panda bears than ten cows,because the population of Panda bears is smaller and therefore the same
saved are of hypothetical people that the subject does not
number of lives represents a higher proportion, and this makes sense
know personally and saving them does not affect the sub-
in the context of endangered species. Similarly, preferences that give
ject’s physical well-being. Therefore even if we believe
more importance to saving 40 lives in an Amazonian tribe of 50 people
that the relevant criterion for decisions about saving lives
than to saving 40 lives in a people of hundreds of millions would not beviewed as biased or irrational by most people.
should be the absolute number of saved lives, an exper-
3Also, the literature on comparing prices for the same good focused
imental subject who makes a biased decision by focus-
on goods, while this study explores both goods and services.
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
jects are asked to provide a price that makes them in-
model in which you are interested is offered with
different between the two differentiated goods. Conse-
two screen sizes: 15" and 13". Assume that all
quently, their responses are on a continuous scale and al-
other features (including external size and weight)
low to compute the amount of money that the subjects
are identical across the two models. Also assume
view as equivalent to the quality difference. This allows
that on an average day you work with the computer
to obtain not only qualitative conclusions (e.g., that peo-
for about 5 hours, and that you intend to replace it
ple are affected by the relative price differences) but also
3 years from today. If the computer with the 15"
quantitative measurements of relative thinking. For ex-
screen size costs [3750; 11250] Shekels, what is the
ample, we can analyze whether multiplying the price by
maximal price of the computer with the screen size
x also multiplies the valuation of the quality difference by
of 13" such that you will prefer it to the computer
x (“full relative thinking”) or by less than x (“partial rela-
with the larger screen? _________ Shekels
tive thinking”). In three scenarios used in the experimentthe data is consistent with full relative thinking, and in
2. Assume that you can do your weekly grocery shop-
one scenario with partial relative thinking.
ping in one of two stores, which are at the same dis-
Moreover, the four different scenarios used yielded dif-
tance from your home. In store A the products are
ferent results and I discuss several ideas about the possi-
conveniently organized on the shelves and the store
ble reasons for these differences. One idea is that relative
is spacious, clean, and quiet. Store B is not conve-
thinking is weaker when the quality dimension is more
niently organized and is congested, dirty, and noisy.
separable from the good, because then the subject can
Purchasing the products you want to buy takes you
more easily evaluate the value of the additional quality
an hour in either store. If the products you want to
in isolation from the good and therefore also without be-
purchase cost a total of [194; 582] Shekels in store
ing affected by the good’s price. Another idea is that in
A, what is the maximal amount you will be willing
two scenarios we possibly see not only relative thinking
to pay in store B such that you will prefer to shop
but also additional effects, which are denoted “perceived
there instead of in store A? _________ Shekels
quality difference effect”, “perceived wealth effect”, and“perceived necessity effect”, and are explained in detail
3. Assume that you want to purchase a bicycle for your
daily commute to the university and back (the ridetakes 10 minutes), and you predict that you will usethe bicycles for 3 years. The model in which you are
interested comes in either 15 speeds or 5 speeds, andexcept for the number of speeds the two models are
To test experimentally how price levels affect consumer
identical. If the 15-speeds model costs [475; 1425]
behavior regarding price differences between differenti-
Shekels, what is the maximal price of the 5-speeds
ated products, a questionnaire that includes four different
model such that you will prefer it to the 15-speeds
decision scenarios was developed. In one treatment the
good’s price in the scenario was high and in the other itwas low. This tests how price affects the evaluation of
4. Assume that you want to fly to New-York (one-
quality differences.4 In total, 415 subjects participated in
way). You found two possible flights. One flight
the study.5 The subjects were recruited on the campuses
is direct from Tel-Aviv to New-York and it takes 11
of two large Israeli universities, Ben-Gurion University
hours. The second flight makes a connection stop of
of the Negev and Tel Aviv University. The four scenarios
3 hours in Europe, and the two flight segments take
that the subjects answered (translated from the original
11 hours together (so you will arrive in New-York
questionnaire that was in Hebrew) were as follows (dif-
14 hours after the departure from Tel-Aviv). The
ferences between the low- and high-price treatments are
suitcases continue directly to New-York and you do
not need to take them out in Europe and check themin again during the connection stop. Other than the
1. Assume that you want to purchase a laptop. The
connection the flights are identical. If the directflight costs [$274; $822], what is the maximal price
4Another manipulation was the participation fee paid to subjects.
of the flight with the connection such that you will
Half of the subjects received 5 Shekels (about 1.10 US Dollars) for an-swering the questionnaire, while the other half received 15 Shekels. The
prefer it to the direct flight? $_________
goal of this manipulation was to examine whether a different participa-tion fee affects the bias of relative thinking. The different participation
The four scenarios are in different consumption cate-
fee did not have a statistically significant effect. Therefore in the rest of
gories, in order to ascertain that if relative thinking is de-
the article the participation fee treatments are combined.
5A few subjects did not answer all questions. Therefore the number
tected, it is a general and robust phenomenon. In addition,
of observations in each scenario is slightly less than 415.
the scenarios chosen are related to products and services
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
that students are familiar with, so that their responses are
hypothesis is that people consider also (or exclusively)
as informed as possible (asking them about a purchase of
relative price differences, and as a result are willing to
a house, for example, is less likely to relate to their life
pay more for the same quality difference when the goods’
experience than asking about the purchase of a bike or
prices are higher. If this hypothesis is correct, the VOQ
grocery products). Subjects were generally in their mid-
should be higher in the high-price treatment; this leads to
twenties (because of compulsory military service in Is-
rael, people rarely start university before they are 20–21years old, and many start a few years later). The ratio
Hypothesis 1: Relative price differences affect choices
between the prices in the two price treatments was three
between differentiated goods; specifically, the amount
in all scenarios in order to allow a comparison between
people are willing to pay for a constant improvement in
the scenarios later on. This constant ratio was chosen to
quality is increasing in the good’s price.
be three as a compromise between two opposite require-ments. One is that the prices should be sufficiently differ-
Table 1 presents summary statistics of the VOQ in each
ent to allow to observe relative thinking if people indeed
scenario and price treatment, and the results of the t-test
exhibit such a bias. This requires that the ratio between
for difference in means and of the Mann-Whitney U test.
the two prices is not too small. The other requirement
The strong positive effect of the good’s price on the VOQ
is that the prices are reasonable given the range of mar-
is obvious: the VOQ is much higher in the high-price
ket prices for the relevant goods, which can encourage
treatment, and the two statistical tests in all four scenarios
more accurate responses from the subjects. This limits
provide p-values below 0.0001, suggesting that the differ-
the possible ratio between the prices. The ratio of three
ence between the two price treatments is statistically sig-
allowed the prices in the questions to be reasonable and
nificant. This means that Hypothesis 1 is supported very
yet it yielded a strong and statistically significant effect of
strongly by the data in the experiment.
relative thinking, so this ratio seems to have been a good
We may ask whether the VOQ in the responses reflects
the real preferences of the subjects, or whether the truepreferences are different but for some reason responses
3 Hypotheses, results and discus- deviate systematically from them and reflect also some
sort of a scaling bias. One reason for thinking that the
responses reflect true preferences is that, when responsesare affected by a scaling bias, they are likely to be sen-
3.1 Relative thinking with differentiated
sitive to the elicitation method, but the literature docu-
ments behavior of relative thinking in studies that elicitedresponses in many ways. For example, Tversky and Kah-
In each of the four questions in the experiment, the sub-
neman (1981) asked subjects whether they would drive
ject is given the price of the high-quality good, and is
20 minutes to another store for a $5 savings, and obtained
asked to provide the maximal price of the low-quality
results that show that subjects considered the percentage
good for which he prefers the latter. This means that his
savings. Another reason to believe that subjects reveal
response is the price of the low-quality good for which he
their true preferences is the evidence that firms respond in
is indifferent between the two goods, because up to this
their pricing decisions to relative thinking (Azar, 2010).
price he prefers the low-quality good, and for any higher
If the findings on relative thinking were artifacts of exper-
price he prefers the high-quality good. Consequently, the
iments that do not reflect true preferences and therefore
difference between the subject’s response and the price of
are not present in real markets, firms would not respond
the high-quality good represents the subject’s monetary
valuation of the quality difference between the goods.
Given the strong positive effect of the good’s price on
This valuation, denoted by VOQ (for “value of quality”),
the VOQ, it is interesting to examine whether multiplying
is the amount of money that gives the subject the same
the price by three (in all four scenarios this is the ratio be-
utility as the utility difference between the two goods, ac-
tween the two price treatments) also multiplies the VOQ
cording to the subject’s stated preferences (of course it is
by three. If consumer decisions are affected only by rel-
not the money per se that gives utility, but whatever the
ative price differences (“full relative thinking”), then the
VOQ in the high-price treatment should be about three
If people behave according to the principle implied by
times the VOQ in the low-price treatment. If both rela-
economic theory, comparing the absolute price difference
tive and absolute price differences affect consumer deci-
to their increased utility from the better product, then the
sions (“partial relative thinking”), then the VOQ should
VOQ should be similar regardless of the treatment; the
increase less than the price increase (because of the mod-
good’s price should not affect the VOQ. The alternative
erating effect of the absolute price difference), i.e., the
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
Table 1: Value of quality (VOQ) in the various scenarios.
The p-values reported are the two-tailed p-values of the t-test for difference in means (allowing for unequal variance)and of the Mann-Whitney U test between the low-price and the high-price treatments in each scenario.
VOQ should increase by a factor of less than three. From
means that multiplying the price by three increases the
Table 1 we can compute the ratio between the means
VOQ on average by a factor of less than three. This pat-
in the high-price and low-price treatments. This ratio is
tern is consistent with partial relative thinking—people
equal to 3.25 in the laptop scenario, 2.67 in the grocery
being affected by both absolute and relative price dif-
scenario, 3.26 in the bike scenario and 2.19 in the flight
ferences. The results in the flight scenario being differ-
ent from the other scenarios suggest that some contexts
To test formally whether the VOQ increases by the
encourage relative thinking more than others. Conse-
same factor as the price, a variable denoted REL-VOQ
quently, in contexts that are highly susceptible to relative
(REL for “relative”) was computed as the ratio between
thinking, we may observe full relative thinking, but in
the VOQ provided by the subject and the price included
other contexts relative thinking may be weaker, leading
in the scenario. For example, if a subject in the low-
price flight scenario (where the direct flight costs $274)
It should be emphasized, however, that even partial
answers that he prefers the flight with the connection up
relative thinking is inconsistent with the traditional as-
to a price of $250, then REL-VOQ = $24/$274 = 0.088.
sumptions of economic theory, because when choosing
If people exhibit full relative thinking, the value of REL-
between differentiated goods one should consider only
VOQ should be the same in the low-price and high-price
absolute price differences, as explained in more detail in
treatments. This equality is tested for each scenario sep-
the introduction. The results in the three scenarios that
arately using both a t-test for difference in means and a
are consistent with full relative thinking are even more
Mann-Whitney U test. The results of these tests are re-
striking. While economic theory suggests that only ab-
solute price differences should matter, in these scenarios
In scenarios 1, 2, and 3 we cannot reject at the 5% sig-
we cannot reject the hypothesis that absolute differences
nificance level the hypothesis that the variable REL-VOQ
have no effect at all and only relative price differences
has the same mean in both price treatments. This means
that in these scenarios the data are consistent with full rel-ative thinking—i.e., people consider only relative price
differences. In scenario 4 (the flight scenario), on the
other hand, we can reject the hypothesis that the mean ofREL-VOQ is the same in the two price treatments. REL-
A closer look at the data shows that also the grocery store
VOQ is higher in the low-price treatment there, which
scenario exhibits less relative thinking than the laptop and
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
Table 2: Full or partial relative thinking?
∗ Allowing for unequal variance.
bike scenarios. As mentioned earlier, the ratio between
that were present in the grocery store. This is not the case
the mean VOQ in the high-price treatment and the low-
with a laptop screen or a bike’s speeds. Therefore also in
price treatment is equal to 3.25 in the laptop scenario,
the grocery scenario the quality dimension is more sepa-
2.67 in the grocery scenario, 3.26 in the bike scenario and
rable from the good than in the laptop and bike scenarios,
2.19 in the flight scenario. The ratios of the medians of
which may be the reason why relative thinking is weaker
the two treatments are 3.00 in the laptop scenario, 1.86 in
the grocery scenario, 3.40 in the bike scenario and 2.04 in
Second, in the laptop and bike scenarios we possibly
the flight scenario. We can see that the ratio in the laptop
see additional effects on top of relative thinking. This
and bike scenarios is at least three in all cases, whereas in
can also explain why the ratio of VOQ in these scenar-
the grocery and flight scenario it is always less than three.
ios is even larger than the ratio of the prices (three). Let
That is, in the laptop and bike scenarios the ratio in VOQ
us call the effects “perceived quality difference effect”,
exceeds the price ratio between the treatments (which is
“perceived wealth effect”, and “perceived necessity ef-
three), whereas in the grocery and flight scenarios the op-
fect”. The “perceived quality difference effect” means
that the subject perceives a higher quality difference be-
Why is the effect of the price treatment stronger in the
tween the low-quality and high-quality goods (e.g., 13"
laptop and bike scenarios than in the grocery and flight
and 15" screen laptops) when the good’s price is higher,
scenarios? Several potential reasons might contribute to
because he infers from a higher price that the good’s qual-
these results. First, when the quality dimension is more
ity is higher (even though the experiment is between sub-
easily separable from the good, this may trigger relative
jects), and then he attributes a higher value to the dif-
thinking less, because the subject can more easily eval-
ference between the low-quality and high-quality goods.6
uate the value of the additional quality in isolation from
For example, a subject who considers the expensive lap-
the good. When he can think about the quality separately
top may assume that it is of a very high quality and at-
from the good, the subject may tend less to determine the
tributes a high value to the difference between 13" and
value of quality based on the good’s price, which is the
15" screens, whereas a subject who considers the cheaper
source of relative thinking here. We can think about the
laptop assumes a lower quality of the laptop and there-
value of wasting three hours of our time in an airport and
fore also of the screen, and consequently he also values
separate this characteristic of the flight more easily than
the difference between 13" and 15" by a smaller amount.
we can separate screen size from a laptop or the number
A similar argument can be made about the quality of the
of speeds from a bike. We are more used to considering
speeds in the bike.7 However, a similar logic is irrelevant
the value of our time in isolation from a flight than we are
in the grocery store and flight scenarios. The value of
used to considering the value of speeds in isolation froma bike, for example. This may be the reason that in the
6See for example Hamilton and Chernev (2010) on the impact of
flight scenario we observe a weaker relative thinking than
price image on consumer evaluation of products.
7An important reason why a higher perceived quality may result in
in the laptop and bike scenarios. In the grocery store sce-
a higher value for a certain improvement (e.g., in screen size) is that a
nario, the store’s organization and cleanliness are clearly
subject may think that he will use the good more often and for a longer
an inherent part of the shopping experience, but they are
period when its quality is higher. To mitigate this possibility, the word-
not part of the goods themselves. Once we finished our
ing of the scenarios states clearly how much time the subject shouldexpect to use the good (e.g., five hours a day for three years in the lap-
shopping trip and we are driving back home, we have the
top scenario, and a ten-minute ride twice a day for three years in the
same goods in our baskets, regardless of the conditions
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
avoiding a connection is not higher when you pay more
The “perceived necessity effect” is the idea that, when
for the flight ticket.8 The value of spending an hour in a
a subject is being told that he wants to spend a lot of
more pleasant store is unrelated to how much you pay in
money on a good, he may interpret it to mean that the
good is very important for him, and as a result also be
The “perceived wealth effect” captures the idea that a
willing to spend more money to upgrade the good to its
subject who is told to imagine spending a lot of money on
high-quality version. For example, a subject may think
a good may say to himself something along the lines of “if
“If I spend a large amount of 11250 Shekels on a lap-
I am so wealthy that I can spend so much on a good, then
top, then it must be very important to me, in which case it
I can also spend a lot on getting the better version of that
also worth a lot to get the 15" screen”. The wording of the
good”. That is, the higher the price the subject is asked to
laptop and bike scenarios that includes how often and for
consider, the more wealthy the subject imagines himself.
how many years the subject should expect to use the good
This is more relevant in these situations where the prices
are supposed to mitigate this effect, but possibly it still ex-
that people pay for a good are more closely related to
ists, at least for some subjects. In the flight scenario this
their wealth. People who buy more expensive laptops and
perceived necessity effect is irrelevant. First, similar to
bikes are probably wealthier on average than those who
the argument made earlier, the flight’s price may be a re-
buy the cheaper versions.9 Therefore telling a subject to
sult of issues other than the flight’s importance. Second,
imagine buying a 11250-Shekels laptop may result in him
even if one views a certain flight as important, it still does
viewing himself as richer than someone who considers
not mean that avoiding a connection becomes important
buying a 3750-Shekels laptop. Consequently, the former
as well. In the grocery store scenario, spending more does
subject may also be willing to pay more for the upgrade
not mean more important purchases (for similar reasons
from 13" to 15". In the case of flights, on the other hand,
to those discussed earlier), and even if one purchases im-
what someone pays is usually determined mostly by the
portant goods it does not imply that the convenience of
question to which destination he wants to fly and in which
dates; his wealth does not have the same effect that it hasin other consumption categories. Similarly, in the gro-cery shopping scenario making a larger purchase can re-
sult from many different reasons that are unrelated to the
consumer’s wealth. For example, a wealthier consumermay eat in restaurants more often and therefore purchase
The article examines decision making in a very com-
less in the grocery store. The amount spent can also re-
mon consumer problem, in which a consumer is faced
flect the quantity of food that one consumes, which vary
with differentiated goods or services that differ in price
significantly between people in a manner that is unrelated
and quality. Indeed, almost any time we want to pur-
to wealth. Some students go to their parents’ house every
chase something we can choose from several alternatives
weekend (this is common for Israeli students) and then
with different prices and quality levels. The study finds a
they do not need as much food so they can purchase less.
strong decision making bias: when people consider dif-
Some consumers buy in the grocery store also non-food
ferentiated goods or services they are affected by relative
items such as toothpaste and soap, while others purchase
price differences even in situations where economic the-
such items in other stores. Some people may purchase
ory suggests that only absolute price differences matter, a
also for their roommate, or shop less frequently, result-
behavior that was denoted “relative thinking”. This result
ing in larger amounts per shopping trip. Consequently,
is documented in four different scenarios taken from dif-
the amount the subject is told to imagine spending in the
ferent consumption categories. In three of the four sce-
grocery store should not affect how rich the subject views
narios, the hypothesis that people exhibit “full relative
himself. Therefore in the flight and grocery store scenar-
thinking” (they consider only relative price differences
ios the possible effect of perceived wealth is irrelevant.
and pay no attention at all to absolute price differences)
8First, the price of a flight ticket is not so much a signal about the
cannot be rejected. In one scenario there is evidence that
airline quality as a laptop or bike price is about the good’s quality; qual-
people exhibit “partial relative thinking”—being affected
ity differences between airlines are not as big as differences between
by both relative and absolute price differences. Some
computers or bikes, and price variation for airline tickets is often more
ideas about the possible reasons for differences between
a function of demand and supply conditions, the time of the year andsimilar consideration than of the airline quality. Second, even if the
the scenarios are discussed. One idea is that relative
subject does associate a higher flight price with a higher quality, it is
thinking is weaker when the quality dimension is more
not clear why the airline quality should have any impact on the value of
separable from the good, because then the subject can
avoiding spending three hours in a connection stop.
more easily evaluate the value of the additional quality
9It should be pointed out, however, that in the bike scenario even
the more expensive bike, which was slightly above $300, is relatively
in isolation from the good and therefore also without be-
ing affected by the good’s price. Another idea is that in
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
the laptop and bike scenarios we possibly see additional
even if the absolute amount saved is the same. Conse-
effects in addition to relative thinking; these effects are
quently, they behave as if their search or transportation
denoted “perceived quality difference effect”, “perceived
costs are an increasing function of the good’s price. Once
wealth effect”, and “perceived necessity effect”, and are
firms respond to this behavior, price dispersion indeed be-
comes positively correlated with the good’s price.
The results thus challenge the common assumptions in
One additional example for how businesses may re-
economic theory about how people choose between dif-
spond to relative thinking is in the context of the opti-
ferentiated goods. Consequently, this study improves our
mal set of products to offer to customers. Suppose that a
understanding of consumer decision making and offers
firm can enhance the variety of colors in which its good
important implications for research in marketing, deci-
(e.g., a car or an eyeglasses frame) is offered, but it is not
sion science, psychology and economics, and to busi-
sure whether to increase the variety of a cheap model or a
nesses and managers. Economic models, for example,
more expensive one. According to relative thinking, it is
might yield better predictions if they account for this be-
likely that consumers will be willing to add more money
havior and not assume that consumers only consider ab-
to get their favorite color when the good’s price is higher.
solute price differences. This is particularly relevant in
Consequently, relative thinking suggests that increasing
models dealing with horizontal or vertical differentiation,
the color variety for the more expensive model might be
optimal pricing, competitive strategy, or advertising.
more attractive than if we ignore relative thinking. Of
Azar (2008a), for example, uses a two-period game-
course, there are other factors at play as well; the income
theoretic model of location differentiation in which he in-
of the average consumer of the more expensive model
corporates relative thinking of consumers. Relative think-
might be higher, for example, also leading to a higher
ing in this framework causes consumers to make less ef-
willingness to pay for a desired color in the more expen-
fort to save a constant amount when they buy more expen-
sive model. The quantity sold of each model is also an
sive goods. This is modeled by assuming that consumers
important consideration, and possibly the cheaper mod-
behave as if their transportation costs are increasing in
els are sold more often. Relative thinking is not the only
the good’s price. As a result, the firms raise prices in or-
consideration, but it can also have an effect on the optimal
der to increase the perceived transportation costs of con-
set of products the firm should choose to manufacture,
sumers, which consequently softens competition, allows
and therefore it should be taken into account.
higher profits, and reduces consumer surplus.
Another implication of relative thinking applies to
multi-product retailers. Azar (2008b) analyzes the pric-
ing decisions of multi-product retailers who respond torelative thinking of consumers. In his model, some con-
Aalto-Setälä, V. (2003). Price dispersion and search costs
sumers buy only one good and others purchase two dif-
in grocery retailing. Working paper, National Con-
ferent goods. He finds that the markup on the good with
sumer Research Centre, Helsinki, Finland.
the lower reference price may be negative (consistent
Azar, O. H. (2004). Psychological motivations and biases
with the idea of loss-leader pricing), but the markup on
in economic behavior and their effects on markets and
the good with the higher reference price is always posi-
firm strategy. Ph.D. Dissertation, Northwestern Uni-
tive. The model shows that when consumers buy several
goods, the seller can benefit from reducing the prices of
Azar, O. H. (2008a). The effect of relative thinking on
the cheaper goods—possibly even below cost—and rais-
firm strategy and market outcomes: A location differ-
ing the prices of the expensive items, compared to the
entiation model with endogenous transportation costs.
optimal prices without relative thinking. Journal of Economic Psychology, 29, 684–697.
Various studies (e.g., Aalto-Setälä, 2003; Xing, in
Azar, O. H. (2008b). Optimal strategy of multi-product
press) show that price dispersion is strongly correlated
retailers with relative thinking and reference prices.
with the good’s price. Azar (2004) shows that search
Working paper, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev.
and location differentiation models suggest that price dis-
Azar, O. H. (2010). Firm strategy and biased decision
persion is a function of search and transportation costs.
making: The price dispersion puzzle. Working paper,
Because these costs are independent of the good’s price,
price dispersion is supposed to be uncorrelated with the
Azar, O. H. (in press). Do consumers make too much ef-
good’s price as well—in contradiction with the empiri-
fort to save on cheap items and too little to save on ex-
cal evidence. Azar explains why relative thinking can
pensive items? Experimental results and implications
explain the discrepancy between theory and evidence on
for business strategy. American Behavioral Scientist.
price dispersion. Relative thinking causes people to make
Baron, J. (1997). Confusion of relative and absolute risk
more effort to save when the percentage saved is higher
in valuation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 301–
Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011
Homburg, C., Koschate, N., & Totzek, D. (2010). How
Bartels, D. M. (2006). Proportion dominance: The gen-
price increases affect future purchases: the role of
erality and variability of favoring relative savings over
mental budgeting, income, and framing. Psychology
absolute savings. Organizational Behavior and Hu-& Marketing, 27, 36–53. man Decision Processes, 100, 76–95.
Hotelling, H. (1929). Stability in competition. The Eco-
Darke, P. R., & Freedman, J. L. (1993). Deciding whether
nomic Journal, 39, 41–57.
to seek a bargain: Effects of both amount and percent-
Kogut, T., & Beyth-Marom, R. (2008). Who helps more?
age off. Journal of Applied Psychology, 78, 960–965.
How self-other discrepancies influence decisions in
Darke, P. R., Freedman, J. L., & Chaiken, S. (1995). Per-
helping situations. Judgment and Decision Making, 3,
centage discounts, initial price, and bargain hunting: A
heuristic-systematic approach to price search behavior.
Mowen, M. M., & Mowen, J. C. (1986). An empirical ex-
Journal of Applied Psychology, 80, 580–586.
amination of the biasing effects of framing on business
DelVecchio, D. (2005). Deal-prone consumers’ response
decisions. Decision Sciences, 17, 596–602.
to promotion: The effects of relative and absolute pro-
Ranyard, R., & Abdel-Nabi, D. (1993). Mental account-
motion value. Psychology & Marketing, 22, 373–391.
ing and the process of multiattribute choice. Acta Psy-
Fetherstonhaugh, D., Slovic, P., Johnson, S. M., &
chologica, 84, 161–177.
Friedrich, J. (1997). Insensitivity to the value of hu-
Salop, S. C. (1979). Monopolistic competition with out-
man life: A study of psychophysical numbing. Journal
side goods. The Bell Journal of Economics, 10, 141–
of Risk and Uncertainty, 14, 283–300.
Frisch, D. (1993). Reasons for framing effects. Organi-
Svenson, O. (2008). Decisions among time saving op-
zational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54,
tions: When intuition is strong and wrong. Acta Psy-chologica, 127, 501–509.
Grewal, D., & Marmorstein, H. (1994). Market price
Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer
variation, perceived price variation, and consumers’
choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organiza-
price search decisions for durable goods. Journal ofConsumer Research, 21, 453–460.
Tirole, J. (1988). The Theory of industrial organization.
Hamilton, R., & Chernev, A. (2010). Price image in retail
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of
Heath, T. B., Chatterjee, S., & Russo France, K. (1995).
decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211,
Mental accounting and changes in price: The frame
dependence of reference dependence, Journal of Con-
Xing, X. (in press). Can price dispersion be persistent in
sumer Research, 22, 90–97.
the internet markets? Applied Economics.
vestibulaire migraineRoeland B. van Leeuwen, Tjasse D. Bruintjes en Herman Kingma Recentelijk zijn de criteria gepubliceerd voor het stellen van de diagnose ‘vestibulaire migraine’. De diagnose is gebaseerd op een voorgeschiedenis van migraine en aanvallen van draaiduizeligheid, die niet gepaard hoeven te gaan met de bekende hoofdpijn. Als een patiënt tijdens een episode van draaidui
Weitere Fragen? Wir hoffen, Ihnen vorerst alle notwendigen Informationen gegeben zu haben. Vor der eigentlichen Operation ergibt sich noch die Gelegenheit zu einem persönlichen Gespräch. Information zur Kataraktoperation Sollten immer noch Fragen oder Unsicherheiten bestehen, die Sie zuvor klären möchten, zögern Sie bitte nicht, mit uns Kontakt aufzunehmen. Sie erreichen uns in