Northern International Studies Association Conference “Power, Vision, and Order in World
Politics” 23-25 May 2007, University of Southern Denmark, Odense
Defining, Allocating, Sharing: Responsibility and Accountability in Global Health Governance Carmen Huckel Research Associate: Graduate Research Programme “Global Challenges” – University of First Draft Only! Please do not cite! Abstract
Issues surrounding how to govern health from a global perspective generally do not refer to
government, (one body that has the authority to make, and the power to enforce, laws,) rather
governance, the setting up of processes through the collective efforts of a multitude of actors
to identify, understand, or address worldwide problems, (see Thakur/Weis 2006). Over the
past ten years there has been a considerable increase in the number of organisations that
attempt to address global public health in such a collective way by involving state as well as
non-state actors in agenda-setting, decision-making and policy implementation. Such
collective efforts, have sparked questions of the legitimacy and long term potential
effectiveness of problem-oriented approaches. Although a considerable number of studies
have focused on the desirability of inclusiveness and right processes as a possible answer to
legitimacy and effectiveness questions, there is an important underlying conflict which still
burdens global health governance. It stems from the basic disagreements of who should be
responsible for providing health outcomes, what obligations do these parties have, and what
consequences do the face if their responsibilities are not fulfilled. The paper addresses this
underlying conflict that is manifested in an incongruence between those people, or groups, for
which global health organisations are responsible and those people or groups who are able to
hold them accountable. The very people that live the poorest health, are the least able to
impose costs on an organisation that performs poorly. Those that are able to impose the
greatest costs, through the withdrawal of resources are generally are usually distanced from
the risk of suffering from debilitating treatable or preventable diseases.
The paper explores how responsibilities are defined, both within and outside of the state,
looking at the recent strengthening of the social norms and expectations(Grant/Keohane
2005) as well as how responsibilities can be are determined either through explicit
agreement, or through a global social contract. Finally, the issue of accountability
mechanisms within global health governance is addressed by exploring the potential of
external as opposed to internal accountability (Newell/Bellour 2002).Introduction
Issues surrounding how to govern health from a global perspective do not refer to governing
in the sense of government, (one body that has the authority to make, and the power to
enforce, laws), but in the sense of governance, the setting up of processes through the
collective efforts of a multitude of actors to identify, understand, or address worldwide
problems, (see Thakur/Weis 2006, Rosenau & Czempiel 1992). In the panel on critical issues
in Global Health Governance (GHG), we refer to problems of, and challenges to, the health of
persons and the health of peoples. Over the past ten years there has been a considerable
increase in the number of organisations that attempt to address global public health in such a
collective way by involving state as well as non-state actors in agenda-setting, decision-
making and policy implementation. This might be in the form of public-private partnerships,
inclusive institutions,1 public-agency consortia, or privately funded and implemented projects
within the civil society and philanthropy sectors. Invariably, the number and different types of
actors now playing governance roles in global public health has dramatically increased.
Setting up rules for and executing public health projects in this way requires us to think
somewhat differently about normative and practical issues that surround such ‘governance’
regarding who has the power to make changes and who has the legitimacy to do so. The
companion paper on this panel looks more closely at organizational aspects of ‘governance’
and how this affects effectiveness and power asymmetries (Holzscheiter 2007), and my main
research focus lies on the foundations of empirical legitimacy in global health governance
However, there is an important underlying question which must be addressed before we can
begin to examine processes of governance and issues of legitimacy. It arises from the
question of which individuals, groups and organisations have the obligation and ability and
1 An institution granting membership to all four categories of actors at least one public and at least one private sector actor ( e.g. states, international organizations, private for-profit actors and civil society organization) and endows them with decision-making rights is considered inclusive (Rittberger et. al. 2007: 10)
duty to work towards better health and assist others who live with poor health. Essentially,
these are questions of responsibility and accountability. After all, when the fundamental
rights to life and health of persons are at stake, there must be some framework for
determining: Who should be responsible for providing health outcomes? What obligations do these responsible parties have? Who can be assigned duties and be vulnerable to blame if things go wrong? It is these ethical foundations of global health governance and
accompanying complex of problems which are the topic of this paper. It is hoped that with a
clearer understanding of how responsibilities and accountabilities are determined in global
health governance, that research into aspects of governance processes will be able to focus
In order to begin discussing accountability, we first need to define responsibilities and
distinguish the relationship between the two concepts. While many use the two words
interchangeably, in global governance they are not one and the same. Responsibility and
accountability are concepts that straddle the line between social ethics and empirical political
science. Responsibilities are ethically based obligations and duties which are defined based
on the capacity to understand, reason and act (Erskine 2003). Assigning them to the various
types of organisations and institutions now active in global public health, requires us to assign
moral agency. Accountability on the other hand is an empirical-practical predicament that is
to be applied to agents that have been assigned responsibilities. It refers to a system of checks
that create the risk of incurring costs for failing to meet responsibilities, thus being ‘held
In current debates surrounding global public health and the involvement of the many types of
actors now active in this issue area, the question of how to define and allocate concrete
responsibilities and link them with mechanisms of accountability, has been largely neglected.
Yet, in light of what has been described as the evolution of global public health as a policy
space with features of a political “pasture open for all” (Fidler 2007) it is of crucial
importance. A considerable number of studies have advocated increased participation of
various actor types as an avenue to close legitimacy and effectiveness gaps in global
governance2, however there is an important underlying conflict that still burdens the role of
the ‘private’ in global health governance. It stems from basic disagreements of who should be
responsible for providing health outcomes in the first place, what obligations various types of
actors have if they (voluntarily or otherwise) become involved in global health governance,
and what consequences do or should they face if their responsibilities are not fulfilled.
Importantly, in many instances there is an incongruence between those people or groups,
who’s health is the responsibility of global health governance and those people or groups that
are able to hold global health governance to account. The very people that live with the
poorest levels of health are also the least able to impose costs on an organisation or institution
that performs poorly. Those that are able to impose the greatest costs, through the withdrawal
of resources or political support are generally not those whose health or well-being are
So how has the concept of “responsible for” become so separated from that of “being accountable to”? Who are the various actors that are involved in global health governance today, and how are their responsibilities defined? Finally, who has the capacity to hold these actors accountable, and how can this capacity be utilised to ensure that responsibilities are fulfilled?
To address these questions the paper will be divided into three sections. In the first, I aim to
explore how responsibilities are defined, both within traditional ‘government’ relationships
(within the state) and as part of ‘governance’ (outside of the state). I will look foremost at
how responsibilities are defined within state and then discuss the problems with transferring
or adapting these processes to the global level.
I will then proceed to look more closely at the allocation of responsibilities on the global level
looking at alternative processes for determining responsibilities based on explicit agreement,
2 Or indeed limit efficiency, as discussed on the accompanying paper (Holzscheiter 2007).
norms and expectations arising from ethics discourses surrounding the responsibilities to
“protect” and “do-no-harm.” and a global social contract. I will argue the case for the
recognition of collective responsibility and the role of global governance institutions for
administering the fair distribution of costs for fulfilling collective responsibilities.
In final section of the paper, the issue of accountability in global health governance is
addressed. The critical question of to whom the various actors that are now involved in global
governance are responsible, is juxtaposed against the ability to hold them accountable. This is
done on the example of various types of actors that are today active in global health
governance and is a debate, which, in light of different capacities of individuals and others to
impose costs on those take on governing roles, is of high importance in global health
1 How are Governance Responsibilities Defined and Allocated?
Historically, it is not long since debates on whether sovereigns and states had the obligation to
protect human rights such as health (and other rights that influence health) were waged even
in states that today have well established health care systems and the obligations of the state
to provide basic health-care are taken for granted. The following theoretical account of how
responsibilities are defined and allocated within the state, refers to those states with
functioning democratic systems of government.
Preceding the welfare-state era, sanitation and the provision of medical care was considered
either a private matter or provided by a mix of public (e.g. city and state) and private (e.g.
church and charitable) institutions to which access was often arbitrary. Over time welfare
provision (including health) through the state ran parallel to citizen organisations that took on
functions of sanitation and medical services (Loughlin/Berridge 2001). Slowly preference was
given to the provisions of basic health services provided for through a redistribution of
resources (tax) and needs based assistance: These developments were inseparable from
evolving concepts of justice (not only to provide freedoms but provide protection and care)
and the possibility to express and demand expectations on governments through democratic
institutions. Broadly categorized the responsibilities of the state now lie within the four main
functions of security, rule of law, welfare and participation (Zürn 2001). The form and level
to which these functions should be carried our are determined internally through election
processes, supported by public debate and organised political parties (Smith 1987: 405-406).
Responsibilities of the state towards citizens are most clearly defined by those who are able to
choose the government, or group/party to lead the government. In a system where all adults
are able to choose the government, allocated responsibilities can be said to reflect the will of
the people, or will of the majority. Individuals within the state are bound by the social
contract to accept this will, and at least abide by the rule of law in when seeking to change the
system. In this sense the state has the responsibility to carry out the will of the people.
On the global level, the development of responsibility allocation has followed a different path.
Rather than demands from citizens on governments increasing and being negotiated over
time, global health governance has evolved from early cooperative agreements amongst states
to serve own interests, to organised problem-oriented public health measures. Rights to health
care and obligations to act have entered the scene comparatively late.
For example, according to Lee and others the development of international health co-
operation is commonly considered in relation to three periods. First, the nineteenth century,
characterised in particular by the first international sanitary conferences; second, the inter-war
period characterised by the establishment of international organisations such as the League of
Nations; and third the post war era, dominated by the history of the World Health
Organisation (Lee 2003; Loughlin/Berridge 2002: 8-9). Following the 1970s and the
declaration at Alma Ata to aim for “Health for All” by the year 2000, a new era emerged,
temporally located at the turn of the 21st century amongst accelerated globalisation, and the
increasing influence of the neo-liberal economic politics of global financial institutions.
During this era, a human rights discourses have been used to argue against the decline in the
capacity of, and will of, states and state based organisations to effectively manage issues of
global public health. This most recent has also seen the emergence of new governance forms,
no longer based solely on international cooperation and negotiation. Today, a wide array of
new global health governance (GHG) organisations bring together public and private actors,
some more some less oriented on concepts of justice and redistribution in their approach.
With the well recognised effects that globalisation has on health and the effects that health has
on many other issues areas, the debate about “who is responsible” now concerns a multitude
of new actors and a strong ethical discourse. The invovled actors may be states, state-based,
sub-state or completely independent from states. It is often unclear what explicit
responsibilities these multiple of actors have, or what responsibilities they take on by
involving themselves in processes of global governance within the health sector. However,
actors taking on governance roles without a clear idea of what their responsibilities are, who
they are responsible to, how their responsibilities may change, and ultimately how they will
be held accountable is a major stumbling block for reaching the goal of adequate health for
With the absence of any kind of world government, debates on ‘who is responsible’ need to
1.1 Defining Roles and Responsibilities Within the State.
In advanced democracies, a system of mutual obligations has emerged as part of the
development of concept of citizenship, in which all able persons falling within a certain
jurisdiction became “citizens” and gain certain rights by taking on responsibilities. Today, the
allocation of responsibilities of both state and citizen takes place within a delicate relationship
that determines obligations for both. Hence, there are three directional relationships for
determining responsibilities that exist within the state context, 1) citizen to citizen (this can
also refer to an civil organisation or business), 2) citizen to state, 3) state to citizen. Each
directional relationship functions differently in how it defines the responsibilities of the other
In the first relationship, citizens are obliged to respect the rights of fellow citizens and their
equal access to participation in public life, including those institutions that protect their own-
well-being (cmp. Buchanan and DeCamp 2006: 99). These can be seen as passive
responsibilities. Other obligations and responsibilities from citizen to citizen are defined through social norms and expectations, to behave in a certain way or to care for those in
In the second relationship, citizens also have the obligation to act in solidarity with fellow
citizens by accepting the outcomes of democratic process and contributing a fair share to the
burden of the costs of government (generally through tax). These responsibilities are defined through the social contract.3
In the third relationship, the state has, the obligation to fulfil the roles that it is given by the
citizen, and they and agree to take on. These concrete responsibilities are defined by explicit agreement.4 While it is the third mechanism for determining responsibilities, that of explicit agreement, which is most often discussed and applied on the global level, I argue that the
first two, social norms and expectations, and the social contract, are just as important for the
determination of responsibilities on the global level.
The corresponding mechanism for accountability reverses the directional responsibility
relationship. In the citizen to citizen relationship, if one citizen fails to respect the rights of
another or fails to act in accordance with social norms, they might be held to account by, i.e.
risk incurring costs. Such costs range from social embarrassment or even material costs if
persecuted through a civil arbitration system.
In the citizen to state relationship, if a citizen refuses to fulfil its obligation to contribute to
burden sharing the state is awarded the capacity to incur financial or even freedom costs on
3 As in Rawls 1971. 4 Of course, the existence of contractual law also represents a clear definition of responsibilities in the citizen to citizen relationship.
the citizen. In extreme cases, if the citizen refutes its obligation to accept the democratic
process, its citizenship status may even be withdrawn. Finally in the state to citizen
relationship, if a government either does not, or inadequately fulfils the agreed upon
responsibilities, citizens are awarded the capacity to incur costs on that government, this may
involve debate, protest, strike or ultimately the removal from government.
1.2 Defining Responsibilities Outside of the State.
On the global level, in the absence of a world government, the two way responsibility-
accountability relationships that exist between citizens, states and peers are not easily reversed
to provide accountability. Power asymmetries are exacerbated, communicative action is
obviously more difficult and importantly regulatory mechanisms are absent. Indeed, the very
ideas of citizenship, peer relationships, rulers and subjects can, at first glance, seem far
fetched for the global arena where citizens have little or no contact with rule-makers and the
“imagined community” expands to suddenly encompasses all.5 Still, on the global level,
responsibilities do exist and are in fact determined via mechanisms comparable to those listed
above: firstly and most obviously via explicit agreements, but also, as I will argue, via social norms and expectations and a slowly forming global social contract.
1.2.1 Responsibilities Determined via Explicit Agreements in Global Health
Most international cooperation bases itself on explicit agreements between actors, most
predominantly states, but increasingly also between other types of actors, to take on certain
By method of explicit agreements responsibilities may be allocated through formal contract,
whether it is a treaty, a memorandum of understanding, or by taking up membership into an
organisation the has a pre-existing constitution with clearly stated responsibilities and roles
5 Here I refer to the concept of the Imagined Community from Benedict Anderson (1991).
for its members. Actors partaking in contracts have the responsibility to abide by the rules of
the contract and act in accordance to the nature and purpose of the contract.
There are many examples of explicit agreements in global public health ranging. They range
from concrete agreements such a pledges to provide resources or logistical support within a
public-private partnership for health, ; to agreeing to spend time and resources for decision-
making and strategy formulation within larger organisations. An example of the former
would be the pledge by two major pharmaceutical companies to donate medicinal therapies
albendazole in whatever quantities necessary to achieve elimination of Lymphatic Filariasis.
An example of the latter would be an Association of People living with HIV/AIDS that
nominates for membership on the Programme Coordinating Board of UNAIDS and thereby
takes on obligations to attend all meetings and participate in governance tasks. A prominent
example of a treaty style explicit agreement is the WHO Framework Convention on Tobacco
Control (WHO FCTC) which has now been signed by 168 states.
Through explicit agreements it relatively easy to allocate responsibilities to actors in global
health governance. However, in taking on explicit responsibilities, actors in global
governance may also take in implicit responsibilities through their actions. A pharmaceutical
company that is a member of public-private partnership will certainly take on more implicit
responsibilities than their pledge stipulates, and an NGO working together with a UN
Agencies takes on greater responsibilities than to simply participate in meetings. In other
words, explicit agreements are accompanies by additional responsibilities which are
1.2.2 Responsibilities Determined via Social Norms and Expectations in Global Health
Responsibilities of the global actors can be determined via building up of social expectations
amongst the community of states, epistemic communities and influential individuals that
come to expect certain behaviours once a general consensus (or norm cascade) has be reached
(Finnemore/Sikkink 1998). Here, the state, as well as other actors come to interact with peers
in an situation that can be compared to a community. For example, with the founding of the
United Nation Charter, the responsibility of the state to respect the sovereignty of other states
was established by explicit agreement, however more recently, the responsibility to protect
has been said to have ‘trumped the norm of state sovereignty’ (Grant/Keohane 2005, 7).
Through this norm states are assigned the responsibility follow expectations of “good
governance” determined by the community of states, independent of how responsibilities had
been allocated internally. In global health governance we find a large number of social norms
and expectations that define responsibilities for various actors. The responsibilities of states
are the most pressingly argued examples here. The responsibilities of states in global public
health are; first to “refrain from committing injustices and from supporting states that commit
injustices” and second to act as “guarantors of the own citizen’s human rights” (Buchanan and
DeCamp 2006: 103). Over the past two decades, the development of global norms to secure
heath as a human right has been slowly progressing to put moral pressure on actors in global
health governance to recognise certain responsibilities not addressed in explicit agreements.
In global health governance we often find a combination of these processes that definine
responsibilities. Either social norms can emerge which are then hardened into explicit
agreements, e.g. the emerging norm to restrict tobacco smoking was followed by the
Framework Convention for Tobacco Control or social expectations on actors emerge
following entering into a explicit agreements; e.g. parties to “The Global Fund to Fight AIDS
Tuberculosis and Malaria” take on the formal task of gathering and distributing funds for
AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria projects, but the involved actors also face growing
expectations on assuring that funds are distributed into sustainable projects with low overhead
1.2.3. The Global Social Contract
Finally, responsibilities can be seen to stem from a slowly emerging global social contract.
Although not nearly as advanced as on the state level, it is a particularly useful concept when
looking at the development of global governance institutions and interaction between different
The idea of a global social contract presupposes the existence of a global society formed out
of an interest to secure order and justice for the members of that society.6 It is debated as to
whether such a society exists on a global level, but, especially amongst commentators of
global health, there are a considerable number that support its development (Kickbusch 2004)
or even suggest its nascent formation (Fidler 2007). The large number of explicit agreements
and social norms and expectations amongst global actors can be seen as expression of a desire
to live with such a contract. However, a social contract goes further than these two
mechanisms for identifying responsibilities, it requires a concept of citizenship for the global
The actors involved in global health governance are not like citizens and states in terms of a
subordinate-superior relationship, nevertheless individuals and organised collectives can be
seen as having the capacity to take on the role as global citizens. Such organised collectives
might be states, or state-based organisations, but also civil society organisations, for-profit
organisations, state-based organisations, and collectives any kind that act with a degree of
independence and identity. Indeed any actor that has the capacity to steer its own actions and
participated in global governance, can be seen to take on role of global citizen.
Key to the question of who can be considered a global citizen is whether an actor can ba
allocated ‘moral agency.’ Erskine (2001) argues that it is quite possible for collectives on the
global lavel to be assigned ‘moral agency, despite some scholars arguing that only possible
for individual. The idea that collectives or institutions have moral agency means that they are
1) vulnerable to blame, 2) can be ascribed duties, and 3) can be held morally accountable
(Erskine 2001: 67). Importantly on the global level it deflects from concepts that suggest that
due to anarchy (the absence of any recognized common superior authority) any action in
6 Based on a Rawlsian understanding of social contract theory, whereby all ‘rational’ actors, when placed behind the veil of ignorance would choose to live with constraints for the purpose of having order.
one’s own interest is acceptable and the doing otherwise is charitable and therefore not
connected with the need to be held accountable.
However, moral agency cannot be attributed to just any group individuals. Moral agency
requires certain capacities on behalf of a collective, summarized by Erskine as 1) the capacity
for moral deliberation i.e. understanding and reflection, realised in organised collectives
through a central decision-making authority with the ability to arrive at a unified course of
action 2) the capacity to act on decisions, without being burdened by instability, the arbitrary
power of a few individuals (either intern or extern) or restriction of freedoms. (Erskine 2001:
Actors that fulfil the criteria for “moral agency” and are involved in global health governance
take on responsibilities that, on the abstract level, are similar to those of state-citizens,
namely: the obligation to act in solidarity with fellow citizens by and accepting a burden-
In global health governance today, there are many actors that would fulfil Erkine’s criteria as
having ‘moral agency’ and therefore could be handed the responsibilities of global
citizenship. In the following section, I will take a look at a few of these actors and their
2. Governance Responsibilities and Actors in Global Health Governance 2.1 Who is are Actors in Global Health Governance?
As the interest of this paper is to examine the allocation of responsibilities and accountability
with respect to the recent trend towards an increasing number and diversifying types of actors
in global public health, I am interested in what types of collectives we might ascribe moral
agency in this issue area. Indeed the list is long some of the most obvious being: states,
patient interest groups, health insurance companies, UN specialised agencies, globally and
locally active NGOs, philanthropist foundations, medical professional associations and
medical product manufactuers. Literally hundreds of thousands of collectives with the
capacity to deliberate, act and take on responsibilities.
For the purpose of this paper, I will take five prominent actors that represent that current wave
of interest in global public health. These five actors are involved in global health governance
and specifically, (but by no means exclusively) activities concerning immunization as a
specific global public health issue. They have been selected for analysis here do to their
The first is a typical example of the actor-type “state” or more precisely “donor” or OECD
state.” For purpose of analysis, I will take the state of Norway, which has been particularly
active in global public health projects in recent years and has certain capacities which would
bind it to specifical responsibilities in the case of a global social contract.
The second is an example from the philanthropic sector, chosen because of its high level of
public attention in recent years: The Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation.
The third is UNICEF, an example of an intergovernmental organisation and UN Specialised
Agency, whose mandate is based on approval from states of the UN Economic and Social
The fourth is Merck & Co. an example of an actor from the for-profit sectors whose business
activities are directly concerned with the health sector and is globally active.
The final example of an actor in global health governance is the Global Alliance for Vaccines
and Immunisation (GAVI) an example of a global health governance institution which, in the
case of a global social contract, could fulfil the role of collecting resources and ensuring that
costs of providing justice are evenly distributed.
These five examples and the categories types they represent are by no means exhaustive, but
they serve as quite contrasting examples in a comparison of the ways their responsibilities are
defined, and who is able to hold them to account. In the following section I will look at each
of these actors in turn and draw out more specific responsibilities each of these actor take on
have in the sub-field of immunization according to explicit agreements, social norms and
expectations and the global social contract.
2.2 For what Outcomes are Global Health Institutions Responsible?
If the responsibilities of entities outside of the state are determined through a combination of
formal agreement and social expectations, and at least in part the recognition of a social
contract it is worth looking at what concrete responsibilities might be derived from these
Buchanan and DeCamp write that with a growing concern about global health, the stage for
assigning responsibilities has now been set following three developments: first, widening
recognition and available information on the nature and causes of global health problems,
second a greater capacity to ameliorate them and third, a growing human rights discourse
based on a cosmopolitan ethical perspective that “provides a normative basis for taking global
health seriously as a moral issue”(Bucahanan and DeCamp 2006: 96). However, they
recognise that concrete conclusions about who should do what to solve health problems are
There are two basic moral obligations that can be said are assigned to actors in GHG, partly
through explicit agreements, partly through social expectations and norms, and partly through
participation in a global social contract, the first is based on responsibility to ‘do-no-harm’,
which basically assigns the responsibility to any actor to ameliorate those (health) problems
that “are caused by injustices they commit or support” (Buchanan and CeCamp 2006: 102)
This responsibility can be applied in many ways; for example applied to business actors it can
refer to the responsibility for the well-being of consumers and workers; applied to donors it
refers to the responsibility to be sure that their funds are not used for the proposes of
committed injustices; applied to actors from sectors other than health, it refers to refers
safeguarding against negative cross-sector effects.
Going beyond the responsibility to do-no-harm are responsibilities placed on actors to assist and protect, or in other words, humanity and benevolence. This is likened to social
responsibility which is multidimensional and goes beyond just being respectful of others to
encompass solidarity with others and working towards achieving positive human rights for all.
As mentioned above, the responsibility of states to assist and protect its own citizens has
become strong enough to justify intervention in some cases. But in global health governance
this does not just refer to states, but all organizations who have the capacity to assist those that
cannot help themselves. Some examples are that several NGOs have their main aim to gain
awareness of health crises and call states and other large organisations into action, business
actors have the responsibility to assist building sustainable communities in areas where they
are active, wealthy states have the responsibility to assist others other through development
Coming back to the five prominent examples of actors in GHG introduced in the previous
section, what concrete responsibilities to do-no-harm and assist and protect have been
allocated through explicit agreements, social norms and expectations and the global social
2.2.1 Case Study: Responsibilities of Actors Addressing Global Immunization
In the 1960s vaccination programmes were rarely included in the activities of national health
services of developing countries and often many years lapsed between the development of
new vaccines with the potential of relatively cheap widespread coverage and their actual
widespread use in immunisation programmes. In 1972 the WHO declared the establishment of
immunisation programmes a priority and in 1974 the World Health Assembly created the
Expanded Programme on Immunisation, and made the recommendation that WHO member-
states develop immunisation programmes against several diseases. UNICEF worked with the
programme as an operational partner. By 1991, the WHO and UNICEF reported that the goal
of immunising 80 percent of the world’s children had been achieved.
After that, rates of immunisation stabilised and in some countries actually fell for several
years and by 2000 both the WHO and UNICEF had considerably reduced the resources being
put into immunisation programmes (Weeks 2000: 2-4). Many donor-states had come to rely
on bi-lateral programmes for immunisation. Around the turn of this century a new drive to
boost immunization coverage saw the establishment of new public-private partnerships and
global governance institutions with the aim of significantly increasing immunization
coverage. The number and types of actors involved in this sub-sector dramatically increased
including not only those with a direct interest, e.g. states with low rates of coverage or vaccine
manufacturers but also those various donors and partners from non-health sectors. The state
of Norway, Merck &Co., the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation, UNICEF and GAVI are five
such actors. How are their responsibilities for action on immunization defined through explicit
agreements, social norms and expectations and the social contract? Below I will give a brief
account of how some of the responsibilities of these actors are defined.
Norway, has one of the highest per capita incomes in the world and high rates of
immunization of its own population. It has taken on considerable responsibilities via explicit
agreements, pledging high levels of funding for UNICEF, the World Health Organisation,
other health based projects and offering debt relief for several poor countries under certain
conditions. As a member of the OECD Development Assistance Committee (DAC) Norway
is embedded in considerable social norms and expectation on how much development aid
should be administered, and how it should be prioritized distributed. Specifically, the norm of
do-no-harm is particularly strong. Norway has the implicit responsibility to ensure that their
aid projects to not contribute worsening pressing health sector problems that hinder
immunization activities such as personnel shortages or inflation. Through the social contract
Norway is expected to show solidarity and a willingness to contribute its fair share to the
burden of global immunization. This may be measured on a combination of Gross National
Income as a percentage of global national income, relative to population.
Merck and Co. is directly involved in the vaccine manufacture. As a private actor it is not
elected by any public constituency that determines it responsibilities, still, Merck & Co.
dispose of a considerable share of the knowledge and financial resources required to achieve
increased immunization rates. This makes Merck & Co. an actor with a high capacity to share
burden. Merck and Co. has entered into a large number of explicit agreements to take on
responsibilities for health and immunization globally. These include commitments to assist
patients that fulfil needs criteria, pledging to donate large quantities of medicines and
vaccines and entering into price agreements. As a prominent and highly profitable actor,
considerable responsibilities have been placed upon Merck and Co. through social norms and
expectation. First and foremost, these come under the category of do-no-harm and activities of
“Corporate Social Responsibility”. Through the social contract, Merck & Co is expected to
use its capacity to contribute to increased immunization rates to surrendering some of its
comparative advantage in knowledge and financial resources.
The Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation (B&MG Foundation) has an endowment of
$US334billion, mostly stemming from the personal wealth of Bill and Melinda Gates and Ted
Turner. The foundation has become a prominent player in global public health due to the
enormous funds committed to various public health projects and the outspoken promotion of
issue-specific narrow-target health projects as good “investments” in public health. The
B&MG Foundation have entered numerous explicit agreements to commit funds, but has also
entered into roles of strategic importance for example at GAVI. Here they have the explicit
responsibility to “make an active and effective contribution to the Board’s collective
performance”7. There are considerable responsibilities placed on B&MG Foundation from
social norms and expectation, often aimed at principles of do-no-harm considering the
commitment of the foundation to very specific narrow approaches. Within the global social
contract, the B&MG Foundation resources should contribute to burden sharing, but there is no
7 Information accessed online 22. May 2007 at: http://www.gavialliance.org/Governance/gaviboard_functions_operations.php
specific responsibility to focus more on health or immunization than other pressing global
problems. Boosting the funds of coordinating global governance institutions could be
considered the most appropriate method of contributing to burden sharing.
UNICEF is a specialised UN-Agency and can be considered a global governance institution in
that various other global citizens participate in the central decision-making structures and
operations of the organisation. With its capacity to deliberate and come to decisions, as well
as having an identity greater than the sum of its parts, UNICEF can be assigned moral agency
and have responsibilities. The reduction in funding for immunization programmes in the mid-
1990s is an example of how UNICEF set priorities and acts upon them. Still, the capacity to
contribute to burden sharing is often limited to allocated funds and resources. Today only
around half of UNICEF incomes comes from public sources such the UN Economic and
Social Council members. UNICEF has explicitly agreed to combine immunization
programmes with micro-nutrient supplements to work towards specific targets in
immunization coverage. It has also agreed to take on the tasks of vaccine procurement for
GAVI. The social norms and expectations that surround UNICEF’s immunization work relate
(amongst others) to keeping appropriate relationships with other relevant actors, and
exercising restraint in adopting approaches demanded by resource rich donors. UNICEF’s
role in the social contract is not only to contribute to burden sharing, but to coordinate and fair
Finally, the Global Alliance for Vaccinnes and Immunization is an inclusive global
governance organisation. These organisations are said to be “obliged to create or collect
resources needed for the fulfilment of collective responsibilities and ensure that the costs of
fulfilling those responsibilities are distributed fairly (Buchanan and DeCamp 2006: 100)”.
GAVI has a clear role on the global social contract, although this is not the specific
responsibility that it has taken on through explicit agreement: which is to: To provide cash
support for countries with GNI per capita of less than $1000 for immunization programmes.
The responsibilities of GAVI determined through social expectation and norms as to ensure
the coordinated projects are sustainable and meet the needs of those that require
immunization, rather than the needs and priorities of those that donate funds.
These are just a few consideration of how responsibilities are defined different through the
three mechanisms explicit agreement, social norms and expectation and the social contract
and are summarized in the following table.
Table 1: Responsibilities of Example Actors in Immunization
Mechanism Explicit Agreement Social Norms and Global Social through which Responsibilities Expectations Contract responsibilities Responsibilities Responsibilities are determined Example Actor Norway
• Use full capacity to reach own aim of
• Fulfil allocated roles as board member
• Fulfil allocated roles a board member
The table above demonstrates that each of these actors have different yet clear responsibilities
depending on their level of involvement and varying capacities. What this method of
determining responsibilities does not do apportion blame or define obligations through
processes of guilt or cause. No one actor can be allocated blame for poor health outcomes but
all actors have responsibilities to contribute to solutions. This is collective responsibility.
Recognising collective responsibilities helps to avoid the problem of “duty dumping”, which
is to “ascribe obligation to individuals or institutions without offering adequate justification or
recognising complexities in cause and affect”. Indeed the causes of poor health (at a whole
community of society level) are almost always so complex that direct or sole causes and effect
can never be determined. Indeed trying to isolate sole causes can only serve to excuse certain
actors from their fair share of collective responsibility. It is for this reason, that all five of the
actors taken as examples here are ascribed duties according to principles of solidarity and
their capacities. On an abstract level this mirrors how the responsibilities of states and
citizens are determined on the domestic level.
3. Holding Global Health Governance Accountable 3.1 To Whom are GHG Actors Directly Answerable?
Ultimately, beyond the responsibility to ‘do-no-harm,’ each ‘GHG-relevant organisation’ is
responsible to those that they have the capacity to ‘assist and protect.’ There is no one actor
with the capacity to provide health for all, therefore responsibilities are divided and shared. At
the state level in functioning democracies responsibilities are determined by those who also
have (at least in part) the capacity to hold whoever is responsible, accountable. Responsibility
and accountability is linked by the nature of the relationships found at the state level, whether
it be citizen-citzen, citizen-state, state citizen.
On the global level, the assigning of responsibility functions in a similar way, but mechanisms
of accountability do not. In this concluding section, I will briefly take a look at this
predicament of accountability in global health governance.
The function of accountability is to ensure that those that wield power (whether it has been
delegated or has arisen from resource capacities) are answerable for their conduct (Newell and
Bellour 2002: 5). Almost all actors in global health governance are subject to some kinds of
checks and balances by others who can incur costs for inappropriate conduct. However, not
all of these checks and balances are designed to ensure that responsibilities towards global
health are fulfilled. More often than not, accountability mechanisms have the primary
function to ensure completely different responsibilities are fulfilled as a priority. Actors from
for-profit sectors are probably the most clear examples here. Merck & Co. is listed on the
New York Stock Exchange and the company’s board of directors has the explicit primary goal
protect the interest of stockholders, who in turn can object to board or company decision.
Stockholders have the capacity to hold executives accountable, through internal mechanisms
of reprimand, or rejection of company (selling stock). When holding executives accountable,
it is unlikely that stockholders have Merck & Co.’s responsibilities to burden sharing in global
Another type of actor that is often cited as having “accountability problems” is civil society
organisations (Baker 2003; Jordan 2005, Benner, Reinicke, Witte 2004)), which have such
widely varying accountability processes that their sheer diversity can cause problems of
credibility. Jordan (2005) sites Ebrahim’s three types of accountability mechanisms for NGOs
as examples: 1) “Membership organizations…(that) are principally accountable to their
members and … use franchise, reform and dues as accountability mechanisms; 2) Service
organizations (that) are principally accountable to their donors and … use performance
assessment, evaluation, reporting requirements, laws and self-regulation as principle
accountability mechanisms; and 3) networks of NGOs (that) are principally accountable to the
organizational members.” It is clear that within civil society organisations, as with business,
responsibilities for public health action are rarely aligned with accountability mechanisms.
The case of failed states hardly be mentioned, as they are such blatant examples of actors not
Indeed, all types of global health governance actors are embedded in accountability
mechanisms that do not necessarily have represent a two-ways relationship between allocating
responsibility and ensuring answerability.
3.2 Alternative Mechanisms of Responsibility
According to Newell and Bellour (2002: 5), “mechanisms of accountability can take a diverse
range of forms from formal top-down processes of elections, hearing and consultations to
bottom-up strategies such as citizen juries, popular protest or participatory budgeting. The
purpose of bottom-up accountability strategies is to maximize the capacity of resource poor
While the accountability mechanisms described above consider internal accountability, by
which only the members or stakeholders of the respective organisations are entitled to act as
principals and to hold the power-wielders accountable, the notion of external accountability
can be used to empower those groups who seek out “bottom-up” strategies. Essentially, these
are persons and groups to whom actors in global health governance are responsible. “This
dimension of accountability is of crucial importance, as it allows for the creation of a
relationship between agents and principals that goes beyond the traditional delegative model
and opens the discourse towards the wider effects of the activities of states, International
Organisations, NGOs and private companies in global governance.” (Bartsch et. al. 2006).
According to Blagescu et. al. it creates “…a more balanced accountability, in which the
voices of those most affected by an organisation’s activities are not overshadowed by the
interests of the most powerful stakeholders“ (Blagescu/de las Casas/Llloyd 2005: 20).
Grant/Keohane (2005) in their analysis of different types of accountability of in world politics
offer two types of external accountability which are particular suitable for “bottom-up”
First, peer accountability: where “organizations that are poorly rated by their peers are likely
to have difficulty in persuading them to cooperate and, therefore will have trouble achieving
their own purposes” Grant/Keohane 2005: 9). This can be achieved via regular public reviews
and ratings of an actors actions or performance. Once peers have a greater ability to judge an
actors fulfilment of their responsibilities they will act accordingly.
Second, public reputational accountability, which can be applied in situations where the a
loss of reputation is a considerable cost for an actor. Through techniques such as public
debate and protest, an actor who does not fulfil responsibilities is exposed.
Both of these types of accountability mechanisms require considerable less material resources
than accountability mechanisms that rely on coercion such as the withdrawal of funds. (See
also Buchanan and Keohan 2006: 422-424). However, they are certainly not cost-free. Many
actors and semi-organised collectives are still far from having the organisation, material, or
knowledge capacity to engage even in ‘bottom-up’ accountability mechanisms. There is
however, great room for such capacities to be strengthened.
All actors in global health governance have the responsibility to pool resources to maximize
outcomes. Ultimately, it is concluded that responsibilities on a global level are shared between
different actors. Actors can be linked together in their responsibilities through the recognition
of a global social contract and through explicit agreements and social norms and expectations.
What therefore needs to occur on the global level is to firstly determine which actors have
moral agency, secondly, to appeal to their mechanism of deliberations to recognize their
moral responsibilities and finally link these responsibilities to alternative mechanisms of
accountability. Most importantly, it cannot be acceptable that responsibilities are defined
solely by those who that are able to impose immediate costs and the capacity for more actors
to be able to engage in accountability mechanisms needs to be strengthened.
References
Anderson, Benedict, 1991, Imangined Communiteis: Reflection on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. Revised Edition, New York: Verso. Baker, Mallen, 2003, The Accountability of NGOs, Business Respect, Issue 66, 16. November 2003. Bartsch, Sonja / Huckel, Carmen / Kohlmorgen, Lars (2006): Theoretical Perspectives on Global Health Governance: Effectiveness, Legitimacy, Accountability and Power. Chapter prepared for the Publication to the Conference: ‘Defining and Shaping the Architecture for Global Health Governance - Current Issues and Future Perspectives’ Hamburg, 22. - 24. February 2006.
Berman, Sheldon, 1997, Social Consciousness and the Development of Social Responsibility. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1997.
Benner, Thorsten/Reinicke, Wolfgang/Witte, Martin 2004: Multisectoral Networks in Global Governance;: Towards a Pluralistic System of Accountability; in: Government and Opposition, Vol. 39, Issue 2, April 2004: 191-210,
Blagescu, Monica/de las Casas, Lucy/Llloyd, Robert 2005: Pathways to Accountability. The GAP Framework; One World Trust, London Buchanan, Allen and Keohan, Robert, 2006, ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’ Ethics and International Affairs, vol. 20, no. 4, 2006. Buchanan, Allan and DeCamp, Matthew, 2006, “Responsibility for Global Health” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, vol. 27 (2006), pp. 95-114-
Erskine, Toni 2003, ‘Making Sense of “Responsibility” in International Relations: Key Questions and Concepts’, in Erskine Toni (ed.) Can Institutions Have Responsibilities?: Collective Moral Agency and International Relations. New York/Basingstoke.
Erskine, Toni, 2001, ‘Assigning Responsibilites to Insitutional Moral Agents: The Case of States and Quasi-States”, Ethics and International Affairs, vol. 15, no. 2, 2001. Fidler, David P., 2007. ‘Reflection on the revolution in health and foreign policy’, Bulletin of the World Health Organisation, vol. 85, no. 3, March 2007. Finnemore, Martha & Sikkink, Kathryn, 1998, “International Norms and Political Change,” International Organisation, Autumn 1998, p.887-917. Grant, Ruth and Robert O. Keohane, 2005, ‘Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics’, American Politcal Science Review, Vol. 99, no. 1 February 2005 Holzscheiter, Anna, 2007, ‘Communicative Action and Organizational Discourse in Global Health Governance: Dialogue in Harmony or Battle of Lifeworlds?’ Paper presented at the NISA Conference, 24th May 2007.
Huckel, Carmen, 2006, Global Governance Institutions Managing Global Public Health:
Opportunities and Challenges, Paper Presented at the ISA Convention, San Diego, 22-25
Jordan, Lisa, 2005, Mechasnsims for NGO Accountability, CPPi Research Paper No. 3.
Johns, Gary, 2000, NGO Way to Go. Political Accountability of Non-Governmental Organizations in a Democratic Society, IPABackgrounder, Vol.12/3, Australia Kickbusch, Ilona, 2004, Global Health the Need for European Action, Presentation the EFC Meeting Brussels, 2004. Lee, Kelly, 2003, Globalization and Health: An Introduction, Palgrave-Macmillan, New
Loughlin, Kelly and Virginia Berridge, 2002, ‘Global Health Governance. Historical Dimensions of Global Governance’. Discussion Paper No. 2, Centre on Global Health and Change, London: Centre on Global Change & Health, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine. Newell, Peter/Bellour, Shaula 2002, Mapping Accountability: Origins, Contexts and Implications for Development; IDS Working Paper No. 168 Rittberger, Volker/Huckel, Carmen/Rieth, Lothar/Zimmer, Melanie, 2007 forth., ‘Inclusive
Global Institutions for a Global Economy’ in Volker/Nettesheim, Martin (Eds.) Changing Patterns of Authority in the Global Political Economy, London, Palgrave.
Rawls, John, 1971, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Rosenau, James N. and Ernst O. Czempiel, 1992, Governance without government. Order and Change in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Smith, Tom, W., 1987, ‘The Welfare-State in Cross-National Perspective’, The Public Opinion Quarterly, vol. 51, No. 3, 1987, pp. 404-421. Thakur, Ramesch and Weiss, Thomas G., The UN and Global Governance: An Idea and its Prospects, United Nations, Indiana University Press 2006. World Health Organisation, 2002, WHO and Civil Society: Linking for Better Health, WHO Civil Society Initiative, Geneva. Zürn, Michael, 2001, "Political Systems in the Postnational Constellation: Societal Denationalization and Multilevel Governance." In: Volker Rittberger (ed.). Global Governance and the United Nations System. Tokyo ; New York, United Nations University Press: 48-87.
Keyword Search of Cal/EPA Internet Sites Search the content of the Cal/EPA Internet site and all the sites managed by the Cal/EPA's Boards, Departments, and Offices. Keyword search: http://www.calepa.ca.gov/Search/default.aspx?q=Atrazine&cx=016697183436188592925. Results 1 - 10 for Atrazine . ( 0.39 seconds) Refine results for Atrazine: ARB [PDF] Atrazine Custo
Local enhanced service (LES) Providing intensive smoking cessation support for patients who want to stop smoking Acceptance of Local Enhanced Service __________________________________________________(name of GP Practice) agrees to the above Local Enhanced Service. Signed on behalf of the service provider: Signature ________________________________ Date __________